Comments on economics, mystery fiction, drama, and art.

Wednesday, August 28, 2013

Great Passages From Book Reviews

"Hopefully it will not be churlish to note that for the outrageous price that Routledge charges for this volume, they might at least have produced a quality volume. But this book seems to have had neither copy editor nor proofreader. It is full of annoying typos, especially in dates and names, and it has a barely-serviceable index. Moreover, many terms and concepts are not properly defined or explained."


From a review written by Joel Mokyr of Nationalism and Economic Development in Modern Europe (by Cark Mosk).
(The "outrageous price" is $140 for a 320-page book; Amazon has it for a mere $133--with free shipping!)

 


 

Tuesday, August 27, 2013

Thinking Like an Economist: The Market for Veterinarians

NPR reports today that

There are way more veterinarians than there is work for them to do, according to a recent survey by the American Veterinary Medical Association, as the nation's veterinary schools continue to crank out graduates. 
A estimates the supply exceeds the demand by the equivalent of 11,250 full-time vets...The veterinary workforce study predicts supply will exceed demand at least through 2025.
And what does an economist immediately ask?  If there's a surplus of veterinarians, what would we expect to happen to the earnings of vets?  This is, frankly, something that intro econ students should get right--incomes of vets should be falling.  Yet the NPR story provides no information about the earnings of vets, which makes it difficult to assess the validity of the AVMA survey.  So I did exactly what you would expect an economist to do--I looked for data, and the relevant data was remarkably hard to find.  I found median earnings for 2010 and for 2012 ($82,040 and $84,460, respectively).  Adjusted for inflation, the median earnings of vets fell by 2.38% between 2010 and 2013.  So there's some initial evidence that, in fact, the market has been reacting to a surplus of vets.

But the level of employment also matters.  According to the Statistical Abstract of the United States (Table 616), 73,000 people worked as veterinarians in 2010, while the Occupational Outlook Handbook says 61,400 people worked as vets in 2010.  The Bureau of Labor Statistics Occupational Employment Statistics database reports 56,020 vets employed in 2012, which makes the OOH estimaye of 61,400 look more reasonable.  So employment appears to have declined by about 10.2% in a two-year period.

This is certainly consistent with a decline in the demand for veterinarians, which we would expect to result in a decline in the earnings of vets.  But the implied supply elasticity is extraordinarily large.  The supply elasticity is the percentage change in employment (-10.2%) divided by the percentage change in earnings (-2.38%), or 4.3.  We generally thing that labor supply elasticities in the short run (and two years is a short time for this market to adjust) are fairly small, especially in occupations that require substantial investments in skill acquisition.    The easiest explanation of this is that the market is not in equilibrium, that earnings remain above the level required to equate quantity demanded and quantity supplies--that there is a large amount of unemployment among vets.  Unfortunately, finding data about occupational unemployment is difficult.

I'll admit that I started this investigation somewhat skeptical of the results of the AVMA survey.  But it does seem to be reasonable valid.  And another survey--also by the AVMA--suggests that earnings of veterinariand have been declining since 2007.  But from where I started--with an article asserting that there is a surplus of veterinarians--to where I would up took a little time and a little effort.  Assertions about surpluses (or shortages) are also assertions about price changes, and having that price information is essential to determining whether a shortage or a surplus in fact exists.

Saturday, August 10, 2013

Thoughts on "A Suggestion for Simplifying the Theory of Money," by John Hicks

Published in Economica in February 1935 (V2. No. 5, pp. 1-19), this paper presents an effort to reformulate the theory of money in terms of standard value theory.  That is, it begins with the position that "...the relative value of two commodities depends upon their relative marginal utility..." (p. 2).  He then provides this detailed justification for his approach (pp. 2-3):


It was tried by Wicksell, and though it led to int-eresting results, it did not lead to a marginal utility theory of money. It was tried by Mises, and led to the conclusion that money is a ghost of gold-because, so it appeared, money as such has no marginal utility., The suggestion has a history, and its history is not encouraging. This would be enough to frighten one off, were it not for two things.

Both in the theory of value and in the theory of money there- have been developments in the twenty or thirty
years since Wicksell and Mises wrote. And these developments have considerably reduced the barriers that blocked their way. In the theory of value, the work of Pareto, Wicksteed, and their successors, has broadened and deepened our whole conception of marginal utility.

We now realise that the marginal utility analysis is nothing else than a general theory of choice, which is applicable whenever the choice is between alternatives that are capable of quantitative expression. Now money is obviously capable of quantitative expression, and therefore the objection that money has no marginal utility must be wrong. People do choose to have money rather than other things, and therefore, in the relevant sense, money must have a marginal utility.

And, as he points out (p. 3), one can read the development of liquidity preference theory in The General Theory as compatible with a choice theory approach (p. 3): 

It emerges when Mr. Keynes begins to talk about the price-level of investment goods; when he shows that this price-level depends upon the relative preference of the investor-to hold bank-deposits or to hold securities. Here at last we have something which to a value theorist looks sensible and interesting! Here at last we have a choice at the margin! And Mr. Keynes goes on to put substance into our X, by his doctrine that the relative preference depends upon the " bearishness " or " bullishness " of the public, upon their relative desire for liquidity or profit.
What strikes me as I read his development of this point is the extent to which he actually anticipates the development of prospect theory (Richard Thaler and daniel Kahneman) in this passage (pp. 7-9):


Where risk is present, the particular expectation of a riskless situation is replaced by a band of possibilities, each of which is considered more or less probable…

If, therefore, our individual, instead of knowing (or thinking he knows) that he will not want his ₤100 till June 1st, becomes afflicted by increased uncertainty; that is to say, while still thinking that June 1st is the most likely date, he now thinks that it will be very possible that he will want it before, although it is also very possible that he will not want it till after ; what will be the effect on his conduct ?...With uncertainty introduced in the way we have described, the investment now offers a chance of larger gain, but it is offset by an equal chance of equivalent loss. In this situation, I think we are justified in assuming that he will become less willing to under- take the investment…

If this is so, uncertainty of the period for which money is free will ordinarily act as a deterrent to investment. It should be observed that uncertainty may be increased, either by a change in objective facts on which estimates are based, or in the psychology of the individual, if his temperament changes in such a way as to make him less inclined to bear risks.

To turn now to the other uncertainty-uncertainty of the yield of investment. Here again we have a penumbra; and here again we seem to be justified in assuming that spreading of the penumbra, increased dispersion of the possibilities of yield, will ordinarily be a deterrent to investment. Indeed, without assuming this to be the normal case, it would be impossible to explain some of the most obvious of the observed facts of the capital market. This sort of risk, therefore, will
ordinarily be another factor tending to increase the demand for money…

So far the effect of risk seems fairly simple; an increase in the risk of investment will act like a fall in the expected rate of net yield; an increase in the uncertainty of future out- payments will act like a shortening of the time which is expected to elapse before those out-payments; and all will ordinarily tend to increase the demand for money...

Note that in these examples, the expected value of the return on an investment does not change, only the distributionof that value changes.  If this is sufficient to cause people to hold more money (and less of financial assets), then the utility or value assigned to the risk of loss (or of a smaller gain) must be greater than the utility or value of the potential of a larger gain.  And that is one of the major tenets of prospect theory.

Hicks then notes (pp. 9-10) that this assymetric risk can be dealt with by diversification (writing as he does before the advent of index funds, he suggests that risk diversificiation is much more difficult and expensive for small investors, and will be limited even for large investors).  He suggests that one reason for the desire to hold money (a non-interest-earning asset), then, is the relative cost of holding interest earnings assets in a risk-reducing, diversified form.  And (pp. 10-11)<


The appearance of such safe investments will act as a substitute for money in one of its uses, and therefore diminish the demand for money.

This particular function is performed, in a modern com- munity, not only by banks, but also by insurance companies, investment trusts, and, to a certain (perhaps small) extent, even by large concerns of other kinds, through their prior charges. And, of course, to a very large extent indeed, it is performed by government stock of various kinds.

Banks are simply the extreme case of this phenomenon they are enabled to go further than other concerns in the creation of money substitutes, because the security of their promises to pay is accepted generally enough for it to be possible to make payments in those promises. Bank deposits are, therefore, enabled to substitute money still further, because the cost of investment is reduced by a general belief in the absence of risk.
One lesson here is that if safe assets are insufficiently available, the most likely response is that money holdings will increase, perhaps in unexpected quantities.  Indeed, following the recent financial crisis, money (defined as M2) holdings has been growing at an average annual rate of 6.7% per year, well above its pre-crisis rate.

More on this larer, as I move through the analysis (this is one short, dense article.)